Search This Blog

Showing posts with label asymmetry. Show all posts
Showing posts with label asymmetry. Show all posts

Friday 23 June 2023

Fallacies of Capitalism 15: The Voluntary Transactions of Actors in an Economy

A voluntary transaction refers to an economic exchange between two or more parties where each party willingly participates without coercion or external pressure. In a voluntary transaction, individuals are assumed to engage in the exchange because they perceive it to be mutually beneficial, based on their own preferences and subjective judgements of value.

However, the "voluntary transactions" fallacy arises when this concept is applied without considering the power imbalances and information asymmetries that can exist in real-world market transactions. While voluntary transactions are a foundational concept in market economics, it is important to recognise that not all transactions occur under ideal conditions of equal power and perfect information. Here are some additional points to consider:

  1. Power imbalances: In many transactions, there can be significant disparities in bargaining power between the parties involved. For example, in labour markets, workers may face limited employment options and economic pressures, while employers may have more leverage in determining wages and working conditions. These power imbalances can influence the outcomes of the transaction, potentially leading to exploitation or unfair terms.

  2. Information asymmetry: In voluntary transactions, it is assumed that both parties have access to complete and accurate information about the goods, services, or conditions involved. However, in reality, information can be unevenly distributed between buyers and sellers. Sellers may possess superior knowledge about the product, its quality, or potential risks, while buyers may lack access to the same information. This information asymmetry can undermine the notion of fully informed and voluntary choices.

  3. Coercive pressures: While voluntary transactions should be free from coercion, individuals can face external pressures that limit their choices and compromise their ability to make truly voluntary decisions. These pressures can include economic necessity, social or cultural expectations, or systemic inequalities. For example, individuals may accept low-paying jobs or unfavourable contracts due to limited alternatives or the need to meet basic needs.

  4. Market failures: The assumption of voluntary transactions fails to account for market failures, such as externalities or the undersupply of public goods. Externalities occur when the actions of one party impose costs or benefits on others who are not involved in the transaction. Market failures can result in suboptimal outcomes, where voluntary transactions do not account for the broader social or environmental impacts.

By considering these factors, it becomes clear that the "voluntary transactions" fallacy oversimplifies the complexities of real-world market interactions. Recognising the existence of power imbalances, information asymmetries, and other limitations is crucial for understanding the potential consequences of market transactions and designing policies that promote fair and equitable outcomes.

Friday 16 June 2023

Fallacies of Capitalism 5: The Self Regulating Market Fallacy

How does the "self-regulating markets" fallacy fail to account for the need for government intervention to address market failures and ensure fair competition? 


The "self-regulating markets" fallacy is the belief that markets can regulate themselves without the need for government intervention. This idea suggests that if left to their own devices, markets will naturally correct any imbalances and ensure fair competition. However, this fallacy overlooks the need for government intervention to address market failures and promote a level playing field. Let's explore this concept with simple examples:

  1. Market failures: Markets can experience various failures that prevent them from functioning optimally. For instance, externalities like pollution or the depletion of natural resources are costs or benefits that affect third parties not directly involved in transactions. Without government intervention, these external costs or benefits are not taken into account, leading to inefficient outcomes. For example, if factories are allowed to pollute freely, it may harm public health and damage the environment, but the market alone may not correct this issue. Government intervention, through regulations or taxes, can internalize these externalities and ensure a more efficient allocation of resources.

  2. Monopolies and market power: Unregulated markets can result in the concentration of market power and the emergence of monopolies. Monopolies can abuse their power by setting high prices, reducing quality, and stifling competition. This restricts consumer choice and hampers innovation. Government intervention, such as antitrust laws and regulations, helps prevent and address monopolistic behavior, promoting fair competition and benefiting consumers. For example, if a single company dominates the internet search engine market, it may unfairly prioritize its own services over competitors' offerings, leading to biased search results. Government intervention can help maintain a competitive market where multiple players have an equal opportunity to compete.

  3. Information asymmetry: In many transactions, there is an imbalance of information between buyers and sellers. This information asymmetry can lead to market failures. For instance, in the market for used cars, sellers may have more information about the condition of the vehicle than buyers. This can result in "lemons" being sold at higher prices, as buyers are unable to make informed decisions. Government intervention, such as consumer protection laws and regulations, can require sellers to disclose relevant information and ensure transparency, enabling fair transactions and reducing information asymmetry.

  4. Ensuring fair competition: Self-regulating markets may not always guarantee fair competition. Unfair business practices, such as price fixing, collusion, or deceptive advertising, can harm consumers and undermine competition. Government intervention through competition policies and regulatory bodies ensures that businesses compete on a level playing field, preventing anti-competitive behavior and promoting fair markets. For example, if two competing companies agree to fix prices, it harms consumers who are deprived of the benefits of competitive pricing. Government intervention can enforce regulations that prohibit such anti-competitive practices.

In summary, the "self-regulating markets" fallacy fails to account for the need for government intervention to address market failures, prevent monopolies, mitigate information asymmetry, and ensure fair competition. Without appropriate regulations and interventions, markets can result in inefficient outcomes, reduced consumer welfare, and unequal distribution of resources. Government intervention plays a crucial role in maintaining a well-functioning and fair economic system.

Fallacies of Capitalism 3: The Invisible Hand Fallacy

 Explain the fallacy of the Invisible Hand.


The "invisible hand" fallacy is a misunderstanding of the concept coined by economist Adam Smith. It suggests that if individuals pursue their own self-interest in a free market, an "invisible hand" will guide their actions to benefit society as a whole. However, this fallacy overlooks the limitations and shortcomings of relying solely on market forces. Let's explore it with simple examples:

  1. Externalities: The invisible hand fallacy fails to account for externalities, which are the unintended effects of economic activities on third parties. For instance, imagine a factory that pollutes the environment while producing goods. The pursuit of self-interest by the factory owner may lead to increased profits, but it ignores the negative impact on the health and well-being of nearby communities. The invisible hand does not automatically correct or internalize these external costs, resulting in a market failure that harms society.

  2. Monopolies and market power: In some cases, the pursuit of self-interest can lead to the concentration of market power and the emergence of monopolies. Monopolies can manipulate prices, restrict competition, and exploit consumers, leading to inefficient outcomes and reduced overall welfare. For example, a dominant technology company may abuse its market power by setting high prices or stifling innovation, which is detrimental to consumers and smaller businesses. The invisible hand does not necessarily prevent the abuse of market power.

  3. Information asymmetry: The invisible hand fallacy assumes that all participants in the market have perfect information and are capable of making rational decisions. However, in reality, there is often a disparity in knowledge between buyers and sellers. For example, imagine a used car market where sellers are aware of hidden defects, but buyers are not. As a result, buyers may make suboptimal decisions and end up with lemons (defective cars). The invisible hand does not automatically address information asymmetry, leading to inefficient outcomes.

  4. Unequal bargaining power: The invisible hand fallacy assumes that all market participants have equal bargaining power. However, in practice, there can be significant disparities in bargaining power between buyers and sellers or between employers and employees. For instance, workers with limited job opportunities may accept low wages and poor working conditions due to the lack of alternatives. The invisible hand does not necessarily ensure fair and equitable outcomes in such situations.

In summary, the "invisible hand" fallacy suggests that individual pursuit of self-interest in a free market will automatically lead to societal benefits. However, this fallacy neglects the presence of externalities, market power, information asymmetry, and unequal bargaining power, which can result in inefficient and unfair outcomes. Recognizing these limitations is crucial for implementing regulations, policies, and institutions that can correct market failures and promote a more equitable and efficient economy.

Thursday 28 October 2021

Information Asymmetry

From the Economist Schools Brief


 IN 2007 the state of Washington introduced a new rule aimed at making the labour market fairer: firms were banned from checking job applicants’ credit scores. Campaigners celebrated the new law as a step towards equality—an applicant with a low credit score is much more likely to be poor, black or young. Since then, ten other states have followed suit. But when Robert Clifford and Daniel Shoag, two economists, recently studied the bans, they found that the laws left blacks and the young with fewer jobs, not more.

Before 1970, economists would not have found much in their discipline to help them mull this puzzle. Indeed, they did not think very hard about the role of information at all. In the labour market, for example, the textbooks mostly assumed that employers know the productivity of their workers—or potential workers—and, thanks to competition, pay them for exactly the value of what they produce.

You might think that research upending that conclusion would immediately be celebrated as an important breakthrough. Yet when, in the late 1960s, George Akerlof wrote “The Market for Lemons”, which did just that, and later won its author a Nobel prize, the paper was rejected by three leading journals. At the time, Mr Akerlof was an assistant professor at the University of California, Berkeley; he had only completed his PhD, at MIT, in 1966. Perhaps as a result, the American Economic Review thought his paper’s insights trivial. The Review of Economic Studieagreed. The Journal of Political Economy had almost the opposite concern: it could not stomach the paper’s implications. Mr Akerlof, now an emeritus professor at Berkeley and married to Janet Yellen, the chairman of the Federal Reserve, recalls the editor’s complaint: “If this is correct, economics would be different.”

In a way, the editors were all right. Mr Akerlof’s idea, eventually published in the Quarterly Journal of Economics in 1970, was at once simple and revolutionary. Suppose buyers in the used-car market value good cars—“peaches”—at $1,000, and sellers at slightly less. A malfunctioning used car—a “lemon”—is worth only $500 to buyers (and, again, slightly less to sellers). If buyers can tell lemons and peaches apart, trade in both will flourish. In reality, buyers might struggle to tell the difference: scratches can be touched up, engine problems left undisclosed, even odometers tampered with.

To account for the risk that a car is a lemon, buyers cut their offers. They might be willing to pay, say, $750 for a car they perceive as having an even chance of being a lemon or a peach. But dealers who know for sure they have a peach will reject such an offer. As a result, the buyers face “adverse selection”: the only sellers who will be prepared to accept $750 will be those who know they are offloading a lemon.

Smart buyers can foresee this problem. Knowing they will only ever be sold a lemon, they offer only $500. Sellers of lemons end up with the same price as they would have done were there no ambiguity. But peaches stay in the garage. This is a tragedy: there are buyers who would happily pay the asking-price for a peach, if only they could be sure of the car’s quality. This “information asymmetry” between buyers and sellers kills the market.

Is it really true that you can win a Nobel prize just for observing that some people in markets know more than others? That was the question one journalist asked of Michael Spence, who, along with Mr Akerlof and Joseph Stiglitz, was a joint recipient of the 2001 Nobel award for their work on information asymmetry. His incredulity was understandable. The lemons paper was not even an accurate description of the used-car market: clearly not every used car sold is a dud. And insurers had long recognised that their customers might be the best judges of what risks they faced, and that those keenest to buy insurance were probably the riskiest bets.

Yet the idea was new to mainstream economists, who quickly realised that it made many of their models redundant. Further breakthroughs soon followed, as researchers examined how the asymmetry problem could be solved. Mr Spence’s flagship contribution was a 1973 paper called “Job Market Signalling” that looked at the labour market. Employers may struggle to tell which job candidates are best. Mr Spence showed that top workers might signal their talents to firms by collecting gongs, like college degrees. Crucially, this only works if the signal is credible: if low-productivity workers found it easy to get a degree, then they could masquerade as clever types.

This idea turns conventional wisdom on its head. Education is usually thought to benefit society by making workers more productive. If it is merely a signal of talent, the returns to investment in education flow to the students, who earn a higher wage at the expense of the less able, and perhaps to universities, but not to society at large. One disciple of the idea, Bryan Caplan of George Mason University, is currently penning a book entitled “The Case Against Education”. (Mr Spence himself regrets that others took his theory as a literal description of the world.)

Signalling helps explain what happened when Washington and those other states stopped firms from obtaining job-applicants’ credit scores. Credit history is a credible signal: it is hard to fake, and, presumably, those with good credit scores are more likely to make good employees than those who default on their debts. Messrs Clifford and Shoag found that when firms could no longer access credit scores, they put more weight on other signals, like education and experience. Because these are rarer among disadvantaged groups, it became harder, not easier, for them to convince employers of their worth.

Signalling explains all kinds of behaviour. Firms pay dividends to their shareholders, who must pay income tax on the payouts. Surely it would be better if they retained their earnings, boosting their share prices, and thus delivering their shareholders lightly taxed capital gains? Signalling solves the mystery: paying a dividend is a sign of strength, showing that a firm feels no need to hoard cash. By the same token, why might a restaurant deliberately locate in an area with high rents? It signals to potential customers that it believes its good food will bring it success.

Signalling is not the only way to overcome the lemons problem. In a 1976 paper Mr Stiglitz and Michael Rothschild, another economist, showed how insurers might “screen” their customers. The essence of screening is to offer deals which would only ever attract one type of punter.

Suppose a car insurer faces two different types of customer, high-risk and low-risk. They cannot tell these groups apart; only the customer knows whether he is a safe driver. Messrs Rothschild and Stiglitz showed that, in a competitive market, insurers cannot profitably offer the same deal to both groups. If they did, the premiums of safe drivers would subsidise payouts to reckless ones. A rival could offer a deal with slightly lower premiums, and slightly less coverage, which would peel away only safe drivers because risky ones prefer to stay fully insured. The firm, left only with bad risks, would make a loss. (Some worried a related problem would afflict Obamacare, which forbids American health insurers from discriminating against customers who are already unwell: if the resulting high premiums were to deter healthy, young customers from signing up, firms might have to raise premiums further, driving more healthy customers away in a so-called “death spiral”.)

The car insurer must offer two deals, making sure that each attracts only the customers it is designed for. The trick is to offer one pricey full-insurance deal, and an alternative cheap option with a sizeable deductible. Risky drivers will balk at the deductible, knowing that there is a good chance they will end up paying it when they claim. They will fork out for expensive coverage instead. Safe drivers will tolerate the high deductible and pay a lower price for what coverage they do get.

This is not a particularly happy resolution of the problem. Good drivers are stuck with high deductibles—just as in Spence’s model of education, highly productive workers must fork out for an education in order to prove their worth. Yet screening is in play almost every time a firm offers its customers a menu of options.

Airlines, for instance, want to milk rich customers with higher prices, without driving away poorer ones. If they knew the depth of each customer’s pockets in advance, they could offer only first-class tickets to the wealthy, and better-value tickets to everyone else. But because they must offer everyone the same options, they must nudge those who can afford it towards the pricier ticket. That means deliberately making the standard cabin uncomfortable, to ensure that the only people who slum it are those with slimmer wallets.

Hazard undercuts Eden

Adverse selection has a cousin. Insurers have long known that people who buy insurance are more likely to take risks. Someone with home insurance will check their smoke alarms less often; health insurance encourages unhealthy eating and drinking. Economists first cottoned on to this phenomenon of “moral hazard” when Kenneth Arrow wrote about it in 1963.

Moral hazard occurs when incentives go haywire. The old economics, noted Mr Stiglitz in his Nobel-prize lecture, paid considerable lip-service to incentives, but had remarkably little to say about them. In a completely transparent world, you need not worry about incentivising someone, because you can use a contract to specify their behaviour precisely. It is when information is asymmetric and you cannot observe what they are doing (is your tradesman using cheap parts? Is your employee slacking?) that you must worry about ensuring that interests are aligned.

Such scenarios pose what are known as “principal-agent” problems. How can a principal (like a manager) get an agent (like an employee) to behave how he wants, when he cannot monitor them all the time? The simplest way to make sure that an employee works hard is to give him some or all of the profit. Hairdressers, for instance, will often rent a spot in a salon and keep their takings for themselves.

But hard work does not always guarantee success: a star analyst at a consulting firm, for example, might do stellar work pitching for a project that nonetheless goes to a rival. So, another option is to pay “efficiency wages”. Mr Stiglitz and Carl Shapiro, another economist, showed that firms might pay premium wages to make employees value their jobs more highly. This, in turn, would make them less likely to shirk their responsibilities, because they would lose more if they were caught and got fired. That insight helps to explain a fundamental puzzle in economics: when workers are unemployed but want jobs, why don’t wages fall until someone is willing to hire them? An answer is that above-market wages act as a carrot, the resulting unemployment, a stick.

And this reveals an even deeper point. Before Mr Akerlof and the other pioneers of information economics came along, the discipline assumed that in competitive markets, prices reflect marginal costs: charge above cost, and a competitor will undercut you. But in a world of information asymmetry, “good behaviour is driven by earning a surplus over what one could get elsewhere,” according to Mr Stiglitz. The wage must be higher than what a worker can get in another job, for them to want to avoid the sack; and firms must find it painful to lose customers when their product is shoddy, if they are to invest in quality. In markets with imperfect information, price cannot equal marginal cost.

The concept of information asymmetry, then, truly changed the discipline. Nearly 50 years after the lemons paper was rejected three times, its insights remain of crucial relevance to economists, and to economic policy. Just ask any young, black Washingtonian with a good credit score who wants to find a job.